Previous | | Next | | E-Mail | | Contents | | V&FT


The Christmas Conspiracy!


THREE: "THE LAW AND THE PROPHETS: ABOLISHED OR CONFIRMED?

LAW

THE THIRD ARCHETYPE

"'. . . that He may teach us about His ways
And that we may walk in His paths.'
For from Zion will go forth the Law
Even the Word of God from Jerusalem
."
Micah 4:2


THEONOMY vs. AUTONOMY


The material in this column is a shameless wholesale rip-off of chapter 14 of Greg Bahnsen's book, Theonomy in Christian Ethics. The links and definitions in this column are designed to help the reader understand Bahnsen's material, as well as promote Vine & Fig Tree's radical agenda, which we call The Christmas Conspiracy.
THE foregoing sections have explained the principle of theonomy in its covenantal context based on the special revelation of God. God’s law has been shown to be indispensable to Christian biblical ethics. Based on the absolute authority of God, and in response to His gracious salvation, the Christian is taught what God requires and desires of him by the written law of God. Motivated by faith and enabled by the Holy Spirit, the Christian seeks to glorify and serve God in all his moral behavior by following the directives of God’s law. Such is the Christian ethic: covenantal use of the law of God. Because the Christian has a personal relation with God established by His sovereign grace, wherein the Spirit of knowledge, power, and holiness enables him to understand and obey the moral stipulations of God, the Christian can live a life pleasing to his Lord. The biblical ethic is constituted by this covenantal theonomy. The normative center of Christian morality, then, is nothing other than the whole law of God as recorded in Scripture.

theos = God
autos = self
nomos = law

Theonomy = God's Law

Autonomy = self-law

And the serpent said unto the woman, "ye shall be as gods, determining good and evil for yourselves." Genesis 3:5

 

The direct antithesis of Christian ethics is sin or lawlessness. Covenantal theonomy is incongruous with autonomy, for self-law does not seek to conform the person’s thoughts, words, and deeds to God’s righteousness as learned in God’s revealed word. The skills of godly living can only be acquired by Spiritual reception and obedience to the commandments of God’s word. Thus only the Christian theonomic ethic is true and effective. Adam learned this hard lesson in the garden; we do well to learn from it also. [279]  

Adam

 
Even when man’s life was untainted by sin, his moral consciousness was not ultimate, but derivative; Adam was receptively reconstructive of God’s word, that is, he thought God’s thoughts after Him on a creaturely level. Adam did not look to himself for moral steering; rather, he lived by supernatural, positive revelation. Adam was not without external moral dictate; he knew what was good and evil because His Lord told him. However, Adam fell from his state of blessing and moral uprightness when he succumbed to the Satanic temptation improperly to "be like God." Satan lured our original parents into thinking that they should know good and evil for themselves; they would be moral arbitrators determining good and evil. They decided that they could be self-sufficient in their moral consciousness and reasoning. They substituted autonomy for theonomy.  
The dreadful results are all too well known to us. Man is not morally self-sufficient; when he tries to be he sins and rebels against God, and such is the antithesis of true ethics. Autonomy is inherently destructive of genuine morality; self-law makes ethics impossible. Although Adam’s temptation and fall took place in calendar history, his pattern of autonomy has been recapitulated throughout the history of ethical philosophy. Biblical theonomy as the principle of Christian ethics is a resplendent sight in contrast to the wasteland of humanistic ethical philosophy.  
1. The following treatment in this chapter is not intended to be the in-depth analysis which only a book (or series of books) could be. Philosophic detail-work and highly qualified argumentation have been relinquished in order to achieve a popular sketch of the high points of autonomous ethical systems. The discussion is thus non-expository as well as incomplete in its selection (e.g., the period spanning the third century B.C. to the eighteenth century A.D. is completely untouched). My aim has simply been to set out an outline of approaches to ethics and present key critical questions for them, in order that some general comparative remarks and a fundamental conclusion can be reached in the end. Those wishing background to the history of philosophy can profitably pursue it in: Henry Sidgwick, Outline of the History of Ethics, (with an additional chapter by H. G. Widgery) (Boston: Beacon Press, 1886, reprinted 1960); Alasdair MacIntyre, A Short History of Ethics (New York: Macmillan, 1966); Mary Warnock, Ethics Since 1900, 2nd Ed. (London: Oxford University Press, 1966).  
In what follows we shall selectively explore, albeit briefly, the history of humanistic ethics that we might see the collapse of morality and ethic in its ungodly course.1  
Note [281] should be made of the failure of autonomous ethics (i.e., anything outside of biblical theonomy) to answer the decisive questions of interpretation, direction, authority, motive, power, and goal for an ethical system. What is the meaning of "good"? What norms are to be used for choosing value? What is the right thing to do in a particular situation? Why should a person be obligated to act morally? In what is obligation grounded? What motivates moral behavior? Where does one get the ability to act rightly? What is the aim of moral conduct? Autonomous ethics, because it looks to sinful man rather than to the covenantal Lord and His law, is bankrupt before the demands of these questions. Only theonomy can render a genuine and effective moral system, for there is only one Law-giver: the living and true God. Autonomy refuses to acknowledge this. The autonomous philosopher is misled in his metaphysical and, hence, epistemological presuppositions. Presuming autonomy he does not see the facts of God’s self-sufficient authority over man and His self-attesting communication to man; it is only inevitable, then, that he will be misled in his ethics. In fact, the very presumption of self-sufficiency is evidence of immorality, sinful rebellion against the clearly revealed, living and true God. When man turns away from covenantal theonomy to supposed autonomy, ethics become a vain delusion.  

Plato

 
Plato reacted to the moral relativism of the Sophists of his day; although denying their maxim "man is the measure of all things," Plato ended up reintroducing it in a different way. The Sophists were moral subjectivists who viewed value [282] as relative to human tradition; of course their relativism made moral prescriptions (universal statements of obligation) impossible. Against this Plato developed a school of axiological realism (i.e., moral absolutism or objectivism); he held that moral values were independent of human relativities and acknowledgment. However, correlative to his axiological realism was the autonomy of ethics from religion (cf. Euthyphro). Plato maintained that there is right and wrong even if the gods do not exist, and he held that a person could get answers to his ethical questions without religious revelation. Plato posed this question: Is a certain behavior approved by the gods because it is good, or is it good because it is approved by the gods? All non-Christian ethicists have assented to the former alternative along with Plato. When it comes to deciding or knowing what is good, man is (eventually) the judge, not God. Plato and all subsequent ethical philosophy are indifferent to what God has to say about holiness; moral good will be discovered and analyzed by looking within, by looking to man’s thought.  
Of course Plato’s question was a false antithesis; by setting it up in the way he did, Plato could make God look totally arbitrary or capricious in determining what is good and evil. The truth of the matter is that good is not independent of God. Certain behavior is good because God approves it, and God approves it because it is the creaturely expression of His holiness-in other words, it is good. To be good is to be like God, and we can only know what behavior is good if God reveals and approves it to us. The important point is that good is what God approves and cannot be ascertained independent of Him, but Plato and the history of ethics turned away from this and down the alley of autonomy.  
By a very unconvincing line of reasoning (cf. Republic) Plato ends up asserting that man’s particular virtue is justice, that is, to live the life of reason. (Does man qua man have one particular function? Must that function be tied up with reason and the intellect? Could not someone hold that the [283] appetites should govern the reason just as capriciously as Plato asserts the opposite? Given that man’s observed function is that of living reasonably, ought it to be? etc.) Plato arbitrarily posits "Good" above nonbeing and evil (and he would accuse the gods of this same caprice!). Contrary to moral experience Plato’s ethical system requires him to hold that no man knowingly does evil (universal psychological egoism). And at base Plato’s ethic turns out to be ignoble and self-centered hedonism, for the reason he offers that man ought to be "good" (have reason govern the appetites and spirit in order to gain a harmonious soul) is that it leads to a life which is happier, more satisfying, and richer. Plato’s ethic is adrift from credibility, the facts of moral experience, genuine direction, and authority. Even if there are moral absolutes on Plato’s basis, one has no assurance of knowing what they are: the testimony of the philosophical "priests" is hopelessly conflicting. After all, it is Plato’s word against that of Protagoras.  

Aristotle

 
In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics man’s highest good is considered to be "well-being" or happiness; yet there can only be linguistic agreement on this point, for "happiness" is different from person to person. Aristotle made the same mistakes with respect to man qua man’s "rational function" as did Plato. He also shared Plato’s oblivion to the "forbidden fruit syndrome" (i.e., men often do what is immoral simply because it is enticingly against the law) and thereby held that no man knowingly does evil. Such moves were necessitated by his rationalistic system and false anthropology.  
Even if we grant Aristotle that it is meaningful and true that "all men desire happiness as an end," he still commits a naturalistic fallacy by directly going on to say that "all men, therefore, ought to desire happiness as an end." (All descriptions do not in themselves yield prescriptions.) By the doctrine of the golden mean Aristotle held that the right thing to [284] do was to choose a mediating course between excess and deficiency; due to varying situations the golden mean will not be the same for all men or for all time. However, a descriptive variety of situations does not imply that moral (prescriptive) absolutes cannot apply irrespective of circumstance.  
Finally, Aristotle’s attack on hedonism turns back on his own system. He rightly observed that some things which bring pleasure (hedonism holds that pleasure is the sole good) are still disgraceful and immoral; further, pleasure is not the supreme or "intrinsic" good because pleasure combined with something else (e.g., wisdom) is better than pleasure alone. These same comments could be made about "happiness," but Aristotle inconsistently failed to make them. We can only agree with Aristotle’s own evaluation of ethics as based on his system: it is an inexact science-of little help or plausibility.  

Butler

 
The humanistic nature of Bishop Butler’s ethic is more than evident in that he grounded morality in man's conscience. The dictates of a calloused conscience will be different than those of a hypersensitive conscience, so what becomes of the universal obligation inherent in the "ought" of genuine morality? Furthermore, not being a universal psychological egoist, Butler is particularly responsible to explain how man can acquire the requisite ability to perform what he knows to be right (in the face of his despairing failure to do so in many instances). Denying God’s sovereignty, Butler had no answer except to rely upon autonomous man's resources. The moral principles that Butler did enunciate were based on his observation and analysis of such things as self-love, benevolence, etc.; in basing moral prescriptions thereon he illegitimately moved from observation to obligation. By entrusting moral steering to each man’s conscience Butler undermined the possibility of a self-regulating, objective norm; when each man is allowed to be a law unto himself, moral principles will be superfluous as far as correcting [285] or restraining him are concerned. Each man can end up doing what is right in his own eyes. Or one man’s conscience is arbitrarily selected to dictate standards for the others (depriving ethics of moral authority).  

Hume

 
David Hume wielded his surgeon’s knife of skepticism to cut the heart out of ethics just as he had done with science; both science and ethics were psychologically rooted according to him (cf. his discussion of induction). Moral judgments are based merely in moral sentiment; a person’s approbation leads him to prescribe moral principle. The moral sentiment is a given of experience (as are desires, aptitudes, etc.) and so unanalyzable. One does not rationally support such a sentiment, he simply accepts it as a given part of his constitution or on the basis of sympathy. Hence, with Hume morality becomes noncognitive and closed to public examination for truth. Skepticism closes the door on universal moral absolutes. Hume "defended" ethics by making it as tenuous as science! Because Hume saw moral judgments as rooted in feelings of approbation and disapprobation, prescriptions are not statements about moral truth but statements about the moralist himself. And biography is a woefully inadequate substitute for ethics.  

Utilitarianism

 
Utilitarianism, represented by a man like J. S. Mill, is a form of hedonism; to be exact, it is universal ethical hedonism. The concern of morality in utilitarianism is the man-centered goal of the production of the greatest happiness for the greatest number; good is identified with that which maximizes happiness. Of course, to make sense of this position "happiness" must be computable; yet no one has been able to do this. Morality with its universal prescriptions is again lost in this system, for nobody can condemn anyone else’s pleasures; to do so the critic would have to appeal to a value [286] separate from pleasure, but in utilitarianism this is illegitimate. Moreover, no behavior is intrinsically right or wrong in utilitarianism; relativism and the loss of ethics results.  
The attempt to bolster utilitarianism with rule utilitarianism (i.e., the test of utility is applied to general rules instead of specific acts) is futile since rule utilitarianism simply collapses into act utilitarianism in the long run (by extensive specification of one’s rule). The principle of utility can be cleverly manipulated to sanction almost any act, even those which are universally abhorred; hence utilitarianism is inherently immoral. As with other ethical systems, utilitarianism also commits the naturalistic fallacy; it moves from the observation that all men seek happiness or pleasure to the dictate that men ought to do so. This expression of autonomous ethics is obviously self-serving and duty-dissolving. Although utilitarians have held that man ought to work toward the happiness of others, one can critically inquire as to why he should be thus obligated (especially if he gets more pleasure out of exploiting than the victim gets out of being helped). Mill is especially vulnerable here since the obligation to maximize the happiness of others is rooted by him in the assumption that it is pleasurable for the individual to seek the happiness of the group or others. At base, then, utilitarianism is simply egoistic hedonism. To calculate one’s conduct always for his own welfare is merely prudent self-interest, an abandonment of morality and principle. Inclination, not obligation, prevails.  

Kant

 
Immanuel Kant represents the very opposite of utilitarianism, for he viewed ethics as deontological rather than teleological; intrinsic good, rather than instrumental good, was for Kant the only proper subject of morality. Hence certain acts have intrinsic rightness which is not determined by their consequences. Kant wanted to get completely away from an ethic of inclination; this he did by drawing a radical bifurca [287] tion between facts and values (between scientific assertions which convey information that is true or false about the phenomenal world and moral judgments relating to the noumenal dimension). Facts have no bearing on morality; only duty is to be heeded-duty determined by man’s moral consciousness apart from God. God is a noumenal object for Kant; hence God cannot enter the phenomenal world to deliver propositional, informative, true moral commandments. Yet the only area in which man has any right to be absolutistic, according to Kant, is in the area of practical morality, for god is found in our experience of ethics. God is not revealed, but is the projection of the morally autonomous man; God is postulated as the ultimate moral enforcer. It is not "true" that God will judge the lawless in a final day of judgment, but nevertheless the moral obligations given in conscience can be "considered as" commands from a God who will redress moral imbalance beyond phenomenal history. We might say that for Kant, although it is not "true" that God is genuine Law-Giver and Judge, it is helpful to think of Him as such. The absoluteness of God is found within the moral experience of man; the moral dictates of man’s self-sufficient ethical consciousness are dignified by referring them to a (superfluous) "god." Having drawn a hard and fast distinction between facts and values, Kant maintains that the only thing which is "good" without qualification is a good will; acts are morally right when joined with this good will, and agents are morally good only if they act from duty. It is not enough that the moralist acts in accord with his duty; he must act solely because it is his duty. Kant continues (with his faulty faculty psychology) to say that a good will acts in accord with reason, for man’s sole obligation is to reason. Reason shall excogitate objective maxims with which the moral agent is to align his subjective maxims. The requirements of reason must be met in the objective maxim, and Kant revealed (based on what authority?) that a maxim is in accord with reason if universalizable with consistency and reversability: [288] that is, if attuned with Kant’s categorical imperative. The categorical imperative is the necessary and sufficient criterion of right behavior. If the moralist can take his proposed behavior and imagine that everyone followed the same course of behavior, and if that universalized activity were not inconsistent, and if the moralist could allow anyone else to do as he plans to do irrespective of his position, then that behavior is right. It should be done from duty, with a good will. Even overlooking the fact that this is simply Kant’s word (and view of reason, etc.) against someone else’s, that moral judgments have been deprived of the qualities of truth and falsity, that Kant’s view is built up on an erroneous faculty psychology, that Kant cannot supply the power to effect what reason prescribes as a moral obligation, that Kant’s view of duty-motivation is somewhat artificial, still Kant’s ethic faces insurmountable problems.  
The rationalistic formalism of Kant sought to objectivize morality; yet it turned out making all value relative to the rational will. Kant’s view that man’s one and only value is loyalty to his obligation to be rational is contrived and arbitrary (Why should man have only one value? Why should that value be found in rationalism rather than its opposite?). How does Kant derive obligation from rationalization? Most everyone can see that morality is far more than logical consistency; on Kant’s basis a sternly self-sufficient person would never need to help others as long as he could consistently cling to his cherished self-sufficiency in time of need. In the categorical imperative there is a measure of ambiguity as to what will count as a contradiction when a maxim is universalized; hence ethics is deprived of clear direction. Kant made the categorical imperative the sufficient test for rightness; yet acts which everyone considers to be amoral can pass the test and come out being obligatory (e.g., wearing blue socks can be consistently universalized irrespective of a person’s position in life, hence it becomes man’s duty to wear blue socks!). Maxims which are generally agreed to as morally binding are [289] abrogated by Kant’s principle; for instance, "honesty is the best policy" does not universalize with reversibility, that is, it does not necessarily apply irrespective to circumstance. "Honesty is the best policy" is a conditional, not a categorical, imperative; under the condition that a business is running short of capital and man-power, cheating could be viewed as the best policy, especially if feeding the family is held in more esteem than a good reputation. On the other hand, if someone did not need profits at all, honesty might be indifferent to him altogether. The duty to honesty is categorical only if Kant can specify some universal, value-oriented end for man; rational consistency fails to guarantee categorical obligations. A clever person could use Kant’s categorical imperative principle to legitimize his immorality (e.g., everyone who has a certain set of fingerprints can steal; since the "moralist" is the only one who has those fingerprints, he can continue with his nefarious deeds). Qualifications can be built right into the rule which the categorical imperative legitimizes; self-interest and inclination can be reintroduced therefore. The categorical imperative permits of contrary maxims being universalized, which is ironical since Kant exulted in rational consistency as a supreme value!  
Kant never explained why it was better to be moral than economic; and although he would have repudiated it, it is hard to see how relativism could be prevented from entering Kant’s ethic given the incommensurability of different scales of values. Kant’s notion of a good will acting from duty was muddled; he held that the virtue of certain acts lies in acting in such a way because it is dutiful. Hence, being-honest is not virtuous in itself or on some other grounds; what is virtuous is being-honest-because-honesty-is-virtuous. When this concept is analyzed it is seen to be virtuous because of the duty attaching to it also; hence, what is virtuous is being-honest-because-honesty-is-virtuous because-being-thus-honest-is-virtuous. The infinite regress entailed is obvious -- and deadly. In later development of his ethic Kant came to emphasize the [290] value of free and autonomous personality. But what justifies personality as a value? A scientist might just as arbitrarily posit impersonalism as valuable. In appealing to the "noumenal self" (or transcendent personality) of man Kant inevitably ran into insuperable difficulties with explicating this notion. Furthermore, the determinism inherent in Kant’s discussion of the phenomenal realm contradicts his view of human freedom in the ethical sphere; in his useless attempt to reconcile the contradiction he ended up bifurcating man and using an ambiguous notion of "freedom." In working from a false metaphysics (view of God and man) and a false epistemology Kant could not avoid destroying the credibility of ethics.  

The Modern Shift

 
In a world dichotomized between facts and values axiology has come to the foreground in modern philosophy. Due to skepticism with respect to questions about the nature and basis of moral judgment, contemporary moral philosophy has been considerably narrowed in its scope. Also there has been an ironic return by those who followed in the autonomous footsteps of Kant precisely to the ethic of inclination which Kant was trying to avoid. In modern ethics there has been a definite turn toward voluntarism, intuitionism, and noncognitivism. There has also been an interesting turn made to questions of metaethics and away from the field of normative ethics (which is significant commentary in itself). Instead of seeking to answer the questions, "What is really right and wrong?" and, "Why?" contemporary axiology has inquired into the logical structure of moral discourse; rather than attempting to understand the validity, content, order, consistency and universality of morals (i.e., ethical system), the current ethicist studies the language of ethics in order to ascertain its function and logical status. What does a valuational word such as "good" mean? Metaethics seeks to answer this question. [291]  

Naturalistic Objectivism

 
We consider first those philosophies which have held that moral discourse has an informative function, that is, conveys cognitive propositions which can be verified or falsified. The informativist school is divided between the objectivists and subjectivists, between those who see moral discourse as giving information about objective moral good and those who see it as giving information about the likes and dislikes of the subject who is speaking. The naturalistic objectivist holds that "good" applies to some discernable or empirical quality in the appraised item (e.g., pleasure for Epicurus and Bentham, maximized group happiness for J. S. Mill, or harmony with nature for the Stoics and Aquinas). Normative terms are definable and, when applied, open to examination. This naturalistic approach has the effect of reducing ethics to a branch of empirical science where the proper method of study would include statistics, induction, and descriptive generalization; however, this method by itself is irrelevant for arriving at moral conclusions. "Ought" must play a distinctive role from "is." Descriptive truths of this sort about the world or society cannot reasonably convince anyone of a prescriptive truth without the naturalistic fallacy being committed; to observe what is the case has nothing to do with what should be the case. It is always meaningful to ask if a pleasure, for instance, is good; yet on the naturalist’s basis such a question would have to be nonsensical.  

Intuitionism

 
The nonnaturalistic objectivist asserts that "good" applies to some nonnatural or undiscernable quality in the thing appraised; this position is also known as intuitionism, for it claims that "good" is indefinable yet denotes an intrinsic, objective quality (or relation) which is apprehended intuitively (e.g. G. E. Moore, W. D. Ross). "Goodness" is a simple, unanalyzable concept (like "yellow"); hence it can be recog [292] nized only by an immediate insight or intuition. The consequence of this is that ethical principles lose all relation to the realm of fact (even facts about God). The intuitionist holds that moral judgments are synthetic a priori assertions, yet indefinable; however, he fails to answer the common autonomous criticism that only experience can yield synthetic statements. Moreover, these moral judgments do not show common characteristics of a priori truths such as universality, necessity, and self-evidency; disagreements between people on their intuited moral judgments is an insurmountable difficulty for intuitionism. Another difficulty with nonnatural objectivism is that it is not clear what a "natural" property is for the intuitionist, and so it is not clear what he is denying. The intuitionist’s thesis that goodness is simple and unanalyzable is not argued, but assumed; apparently, this characterization of goodness must itself also be intuited! The moral intuitions described by men like G. E. Moore have failed to have the cogency which is claimed for them as far as most people and their ethical experiences are concerned (these intuitions seem to suffer the same fate as Descartes’ "clear and distinct ideas"). The whole appeal to intuition must acquiesce in the face of many of the same arguments which are raised against mysticism. In the long run it is simply unclear what authority or obligation can attach to one’s closed-to-investigation intuition, what help in making moral decisions this offers, and how this intuition helps one to enact what is "good" behavior. The "odd facts" of moral intuitions render moral theory undiscussable. The content, grounds, and significance of ethics was lost to inexplicable intuitions which rendered it impossible to even define valuational terms in moral discourse.  

Subjectivistic Schools

 
Others who hold that "good" is used in an informative way in ethical judgments are subjectivists. The private subjectivist maintains that the predication of "good" to anything [293] simply asserts the speaker’s personal approbation for it (e.g., Hume) or that it contributes to fullest satisfaction (e.g., Santayana). If this is the case, however, then moral judgments are never false unless the speaker is mistaken about his own psychology; at least all moral utterances are incorrigible. This is certainly a strange state of affairs; moral discourse is informative according to the private subjectivist and thereby capable of being true or false-yet it is never false! Also, two people could never mean the same thing even though there might be a linguistic agreement on a moral appraisal, for in "agreeing" that X is "good" the two speakers are not attributing to it the same property. All predications of "good" are statements about the speaker, not about the object under consideration. Furthermore, the private subjectivist could not reasonably answer to a question asking why he approves of X as "good," for he would either make an illegitimate reference to the goodness or value of the object independent of his feelings toward it or he would end up reasoning in a vicious circle. It is also meaningful for us to ask whether what the private subjectivist approves is actually good or not; yet on his basis such a question would be ridiculous. Although the private subjectivist holds that ethical discourse is informative and definable, oddly enough ethics is still not open to discussion. "Good" is simply relative to each moralist; therefore, ethics is destroyed because the notion of obligation cannot be derived from this conception of "good."  
A modification of the above proposal is found in the interest theory" of R. B. Perry, who defines "good" as an object of interest to someone. In this way Perry seems to deny that there is anything which is intrinsically good; for anything to be good it must sustain a certain relationship with a mind outside of it. Yet it certainly seems that when most people attribute goodness to something they are viewing that object as being in some way valuable for itself; at least what they appear to intend is something stronger than simply "someone has an interest in X." To hold that X is [294] "good" in customary discourse usually implies that others should value it. It is normally not muddled to appraise some-one’s interest as bad or evil; however, Perry’s construction would make it so. How does Perry’s relational view of "good" account for this stronger use of the term at all? Unless an intrinsic notion of goodness came into being as an apprehension of some objective reality, it would seem to be senseless; yet most people do not consider that it is absurd to view certain items or behavior as good irrespective of what people may think about them. Perry’s view must stretch the general limits of plausibility in order to account for the "forbidden fruit syndrome" (i.e., seeking the immoral for immorality’s sake). To explain this facet of moral experience by reference to ignorance or a confusion of priorities is simply not accurate or true to human nature at all. Perry’s view falls into the same pitfalls as subjectivism: there is no moral authority, universal obligation, or concrete direction offered by a theory which is at root nothing more than moral relativism.  
Another form of subjectivism is societal subjectivism; it holds that "good" applies to those things of which the group approves (e.g., Durkheim) or which is the law of the land or which has the sanction of tradition. Yet to say that something is "good" because it evokes the approval of most people has blatant difficulties. Obviously the majority is not always right; moving from 49% to 51% in the opinion polls does not make a certain behavior right. Again, it is not meaningless to ask whether what the group decided upon was in fact "good"; yet on this view the majority or common law or tradition would be right by definition! Furthermore, if this social approval view were correct, then all obligations could be removed by secrecy-which from an ethical viewpoint seems nonsense. All forms of subjectivism inherently destroy what ethics strives to attain: objective standards which can properly correct and direct man’s behavior. If moral principle has no restraining or corrective element, why should one bother to enunciate it? [295]  

Process Schools

 
Others who have held that "good" is informative in moral discourse have not been naturalistic objectivists, or intuitionists, or subjectivists of a private or societal brand; rather, they have viewed good instrumentally or from the standpoint of a process. A broad evolutionary theory says that "good" applies to that which is conducive to the development of new values (e.g., Julian Huxley). Marxism holds that those ideals are good which are adapted to the needs of a particular stage in economic-social, dialectical process (e.g., Marx, Engels). Men like Hegel and Bradley identified good with that which contributed to the realization of true selfhood, man’s ultimate aim. But is change, or a classless society, or selfhood (whatever that means) genuinely "good"? How does one calculate moral directives or get the ability to follow them? Is there anything to recommend these aims over competing ones? Can obligation be derived from such notions of "good"? Such questions serve to undermine the ethical authority of process theory ethics and underline the arbitrariness of their standards. It would seem that any man could claim that his behavior represented the pioneering newness of the evolutionary process, or the appropriate expression of dialectical materialism, or the true realization of genuine selfhood. Who could gainsay him? On the other hand, what besides coercion could motivate a person who is recalcitrant to the process? Since the only intrinsic good is that toward which the process is moving, is it not accurate to say that coerced behavior is just as morally praiseworthy as willing behavior since both further the process? Since any means can be justified by the end, and since no person can presume to speak authoritatively as to what behavior will actually promote the realization of the desired end, ethics is once again adrift from universal obligation and concrete directives and correctives. [296]  

Pragmatism

 
Voluntaristic pragmatism asserts that "good" applies to whatever promotes our course of action or desired ends. Men like Dewey and James, building on the same concerns as the utilitarians, sought to make ethics relevant to man by associating it with human projects or goals. In the long run it turns out that there are only successful and less successful types of behavior; the evaluative difference between various activities is only one of degree, not one of quality or kind. Hence there is really no moral system at all, unless one posits that all men are obligated to act in a way which maximizes success-a principle which is as dubious as it is arbitrary. Pragmatism is not immune from the same type of criticisms which have been leveled against subjectivism and utilitarianism. In pragmatism moral obligation is out of place, an intrinsic good is unknown, authority is lacking, and selfish motivation is the only one known. Pragmatism is simply an unsuitable counter-intuitive foundation for morality.  

Emotivism

 
All of the preceding schools of thought have in some way viewed the function of ethical discourse as informative; however, in the face of the verifiability criterion (which, in passing, nobody has been able to formulate adequately and consistently) commonly recognized moral judgments are neither empirically verifiable nor analytic truths. Hence a major new approach to the metaethical question was developed. It fundamentally held that, although valuational utterances have a grammatical similarity to factual assertions, the function of moral discourse is noncognitive or noninformative. Emotive function was attributed to ethical language by men like A. J. Ayer and C. L. Stevenson; according to them moral statements were really only expressive of feeling and personal approval (e.g., "Hurray for chastity!"). Moral utterances are not credited as being genuine judgments; so emotivism is con-[297] cerned to deal only with the perlocutionary effects of ethical language. This approach does not take moral discourse seriously enough, however, for it is quite apparent that a person also uses moral utterance to recommend to others that they also follow this action (indeed, that they are obligated to do so). The emotivist has nothing to contribute as far as what moral locutions are or say or mean; it is difficult to analyze spontaneous, gut-level, bursting-forth expressions of feeling. Emotivism deprives ethics of any genuine directive value and places a great strain upon moral principles: how are they derived? what legitimizes them? why are they proper or improper? The moralist’s given attitude cannot be open to discussion since it is noncognitive. So it seems that one is thrown back again upon an ethics of inclination, which (as we have previously observed) is really a nonethic. Emotivism can only have significance in an ethical discussion as a version of private subjectivism, and the inadequacies of that philosophy have already been demonstrated.  

Prescriptivism

 
Another noncognitivist reply to the metaethical question has been that of R. M. Hare who heads the school of imperativism or prescriptivism. According to this line of thought moral utterances are really veiled commands; hence ethical language has a directive or commending function. The prescriptivist differs from the emotivist in that he is concerned with the illocutionary "speech-act" which moral utterances perform rather than their perlocutionary effect. Prescriptivism is afflicted with much of the same problem facing emotivism since they are both noncognitivist answers. The grounds for ethical prescriptions and the meaning of moral principles have been abandoned, leaving the central concerns of morality behind and future considerations of ethical direction closed to any discussion or investigation. Furthermore, both emotivism and imperativism dissolve any distinctiveness which moral language once had, for the central functions of moral [298] utterance on the noncognitivists’ view are also performed by other kinds of language which are completely indifferent to questions of morality. So not only is ethics undiscussable, it is simply not a separate discipline or concern of man. The imperative intrinsic in a moral utterance does not even have the arrogance of authority which is customarily associated with ethical commandments; imperativism reduces ethics to simple personal commendations or advice. That is, according to imperativism the veiled command inherent in moral utterance does not have the force of universally valid, authoritative command dictated by objective moral principle; rather, it is merely a personal expression of a desire to have others conform to a subjectively approved course of action. So although imperativism might seem to offer more hope for the ethical endeavor than emotivism, it actually leaves ethics as rootless, subjective, and nonobligatory as emotivism. This approach also fails to do justice to the seriousness with which people use their ethical language; they seem to imply that true obligation attaches to their moral judgments so that they are offering something stronger than a recommendation to others. The sheer relativism inherent in the imperativist’s position is exhibited in his asserting that the descriptive meaning of "good" or any other ethical language can be completely different in every case of its usage; the only thing which is constant is the directive element. No objective qualities can be made the criteria for the application of "good." When pressed for justification for his moral utterances, the moralist cannot appeal to any inherent value (i.e., "goodness") in his recommended behavior; he could never say that it was virtuous to act in a particular way but only that it was imperative! If the prescriptivist supported his utterances by appealing to ascertainable values he would be forsaking his position, and if he said that a person should act in the way recommended because it was "good" (or any other valuational adjective) he would be reasoning in a vicious circle (e.g., "Jones is commanded to be truthful because it is command-[299] ed"). The imperativist can tell us what we should do, but he cannot tell us why. In the long run the imperativist even fails to offer guidance, for in situations of moral complexity or where there are conflicting recommendations, reasons cannot be urged for or against the given attitude of any moralist. Imperativism is another reversion to the nonethic of an ethic of inclination. Ml that which is customarily of distinctive moral interest has been eliminated from the picture.  

Analytic Approach

 
Ethics fares no better under the analytic school, for the analyst restricts his attention to studying the role of moral language in common life circumstances. His job is merely that of analyzing and describing; he can offer no directive help or moral principle for situations in which one is morally uncertain. Moreover, there is no guarantee that the situations which he analyzes are instances of valid or genuine moral behavior or applications of true moral principle; hence, if the analyst laid down moral directives based on his study of the actual use made of moral language, he would be open to criticism for committing the naturalistic fallacy.  

Existentialism

 
Existentialism is preoccupied with ethical situations where genuine decisions must be made by the "free" man. Being disenchanted by the total lack of help the noncognitivist schools offer one in making difficult moral decisions, and being entirely skeptical of all the solutions offered by the informativist schools of ethics, the existentialist centers on the moral psychology which comes to play in profoundly complex and extraordinary circumstances requiring definite ethical decision. The virtues of authenticity and radical freedom are extolled; this fact, coupled with the existentialist emphasis that all human situations are morally unprecedented (a man cannot look to previous answers) and that each man chooses for all men in his moral decisions, puts an intolerable [300] strain upon the moralist. He is to consider himself completely alone and without any moral guidance whatsoever; the dreadful responsibility he has leaves him in the anguish of moral paralysis. Out of such a situation authentic decisions can be made by the radically free man. This is the one virtue: that the moralist acts. The direction he takes in his behavior is irrelevant; what counts is that he alone made the bold decision and dramatically acted. He can help the man who is being mugged, or lie can help mug him; either act, if an authentic choice, would be moral. Ethical decisions must be spun right out of thin air, for the man who makes the "authentic" decision must be free from his passions (for he chooses whether to resist or give in to them), from motives (since there is no psychological centrum or ego to which motives could adhere, and since the agent himself must first decide what kinds of reasons he will allow to have weight before he begins to rationally deliberate), from reality-in-itself (since man, who is being-for-itself, lies outside the causal series altogether), and from any human essence (since existence precedes and formulates essence). Existentialism, then, does not even have the advantage of being an unethical ethics of inclination (like emotivism, etc.); it is simply an ethics of pure volition (or alleges that it is anyway). Man is free from any antecedently fixed values according to the existentialist; value is defined as it is chosen. Jean-Paul Sartre says that the very starting point of existentialism is Dostoyevsky’s words, "If God did not exist, everything would be possible"; based on the absence of God, says Sartre, man has nothing to cling to and all values disappear. Every choice is consequently as justifiable as it is absurd; there are not good and bad choices, but just choices. Sartre has the protagonist, Orestes, say in The Flies, "I am doomed to have no other law but mine. Sartre says of Mathieau, the protagonist of The Age of Reason, "There would be for him no good nor evil unless he brought them into being." Obviously existentialism is the complete annihilation of ethics, for within that school of [301] thought it is impossible to make a wrong free choice. Responsibility and ethic are appropriate only to a world in which there are objective moral principles which can be accepted or rejected, followed or violated. There is nothing ethical at stake in a "moral decision" for the existentialist; hence, negative ethical judgments are impossible and positive ones are superfluous.  

Evaluation and Comparison

 
Such then is the graveyard of autonomous ethics; each gravestone reads the Satanic temptation, "Ye shall be as gods, knowing good and evil." When man turns away from covenantal theonomy to autonomy, when he despises God’s law in favor of humanistic self-law, the inevitable result is spiritual death for man and the loss of any hope for ethics. The autonomous philosophies of man have failed to answer the crucial questions of both normative ethics and metaethics; they have thus failed because each has assumed a nonbiblical anthropology wherein man is not the creature of an authoritative and sovereign Lord-Creator who has placed His indelible image in man and has perspicuously revealed Himself to each man in every fact of man’s environment. Rather man is taken to be, as Sartre unpretentiously puts it in Being and Nothingness, "the being who tries to become God." Rather than submitting himself to God and God’s self-attesting word, man has attempted to deify himself; the consequence of this in the area of ethics is that God’s law is rejected or ignored in favor of a moral law which man himself will devise or validate. Man is culpable for trying to develop his own ethic, for God’s image and revelation are inescapable; man knows himself to be a creature accountable to God and responsible to God’s demands. Theonomy condemns autonomy. The very fact that God has uttered the law makes man obligated to it since he is the creature of God. God’s law is ethically self-attesting; as such it cannot be questioned, appealed, ignored, or replaced. [302]  
Autonomous ethics has failed to supply an adequate meaning for "good." It has failed to supply any genuine authority for ethics. All of the autonomous schools of ethics finally fall short of providing actual moral direction and correction; they do not supply the guidance which man longs for in studying morality. An effective motivation is not suggested in the ethics of autonomy; nor is ethical power provided. A final goal or aim of ethics is either unknown or open to question in autonomous ethics. In one or all of these vital elements of a genuine ethic the philosophies of autonomy let man down.  
By contrast, the ethics of theonomy is a genuine ethic. "Good" is identified with God; anything which is good is God-like. God reveals to man what is God-like behavior; He tells the creature how to practice holiness. The law of God is good, for its Author is good; the law is the transcript of God’s holiness. This law is very explicit with respect to moral directives and correctives; man is given concrete ethical guidance by the law of God. This law is also authoritative, for the Lord-Creator stands behind it and will judge on the basis of it. All men have a clear revelation of God and know that they are obligated to keep His word; there is no epistemological skepticism with respect to morality. Ethics has a definite relation to facts; the same God who created and defined the material world is the Law-giver who demands the obedience of man. Because the world is as it is, because God is Who He is (Creator and Lord), man must behave as prescribed in God’s law. Obligation can be derived from the facts of God’s character and existence. Because the biblical God is the living and true God who shall hold man accountable, man is accountable to God and obligated to keep God’s law. Man should be motivated to keep this law by faith in God and reverence for His Person; in the light of God’s grace and/or coming judgment, a person is impelled to obey the commandments of God. The enabling power of obedience to God’s law for the believer and the effective agent which restrains the [303] unbeliever from being as unlawful as he could be is the Holy Spirit; God supplies His Spirit, who exercises the power of common grace and sanctifying grace. The power of obedience is most intensely and genuinely known by the Christian who, under the New Covenant, has the law written upon his heart by God; the Spirit causes him to grow up into the obedient stature of Christ, thereby fulfilling the law in the believer. The goal of theonomic ethics is the glory of God and service of His kingdom; by obeying God’s law the Christian honors and magnifies God’s name, bows to His authority, extols His wisdom. Through obedience to God’s law the believer is an effective servant of the kingdom by promoting and seeking its righteousness, by enforcing its demands in the world, by spreading its bounds; the demands of God’s kingdom are applied to self, family, society, and church. This then is the only true ethic for man; to follow another is to deny God His due. Commitment to an autonomous ethic (any moral system which does not fully acknowledge and promote the law of God) is a choice of death and curse in the face of blessing and life.  
All non-Christian ethics ultimately seek information and a standard for ethics in man’s moral consciousness; it attempts to divorce the metaphysical question from the ethical. The nature and authority of morality must exist independently of God for the unbeliever; the "good" must be impersonal. Man is forced to find direction for himself; and the inevitable outcome is subjectivism or relativism. There is no hope in non-Christian ethics; there is no promise of enabling power, of sure direction, of the victory of the right. Having no grounds for ethical responsibility and no justification for the consistency and validity of moral demands, the non-Christian ethic becomes ego-centric rather than ego-regulating. Man is not dealt with as a unity by the autonomous ethicists; he is dichotomized into phenomenal/noumenal categories, and there is a one-sided stress on his intellect, or emotions, or volitions. [304]  
How totally different is the biblical ethic of theonomy! Christian ethics is bound to an absolute, objective authority in God; good does not exist independently of Him and cannot be discussed without bringing Him into the picture. The moral principles followed by the Christian are personal imperatives, not abstract ideals; they can only be learned by revelation, never by man’s own searching. The Christian does not assume that the present state of the world is normal or that his moral consciousness is normal; this is the fatal presupposition of autonomy. The believer knows that he needs to be corrected and directed, for he cannot trust his own reasoning or inclinations; even God’s general revelation must be seen through the corrective lenses of Scripture. Evil is not inherent in the world; so the Christian has the bright hope of its defeat and judgment. The power of the Spirit and pattern of the law are sufficient to destroy the bondage and effects of Satan in a person’s life and world conditions. Although perfection is not possible until final glorification, and although a thoroughly righteous society will not exist until the establishment of the eschatological new heavens and earth, nevertheless God is at work in the Christian and in His Church even now; sanctification is taking place, and the forces of evil can be reproved and nullified by the positive forces of God’s Spirit in accordance with His holy law. The Christian is never left in situations of moral perplexity; everything he needs to be perfectly equipped for all good works has been supplied to him (2 Tim. 3:16 f.) and there is no situation in which he is left in utter moral insolubility (1 Cor. 10:13). Obligation to God’s law is grounded in His authority as Creator; His final judgment will punish all disobedience and redress all moral imbalance. God, through His law, deals with man as a unified personality; He makes an absolute demand upon man’s thinking, feeling, and willing, for His law touches upon every area of life. The ethics of theonomy is God-centered, then, rather than man-centered; it will regulate and correct man in order [305] to bring glory to God. Only the ethics of theonomy can supply man with his needed moral system.  
The main problem with autonomous ethics is that it ignores God’s authority and revealed will; this in itself is immoral and rebellious. It should be rather clear, therefore, that genuine Christian ethics must not align itself with the autonomous methodology and systems of unbelieving philosophy. The Christian should never attempt to find out the principles of morality outside of God’s revelation and direction; the neutrality proposed by Plato in the Euthyphro is sin. The Christian is not relieved of his obligations as a son of God when he studies ethics; God’s clear revelation is the light in which all moral questions (as with all questions) must be answered. Theonomy must be central in Christian ethics. We do not decide to follow God’s law after it has been validated by the categorical imperative or paralleled by any other secular philosophical ethic; we do not demand autonomous justification for God’s commandments. We obey because we love, revere, and trust our Creator, never questioning His wisdom. No apostate standard shall be allowed to evaluate and pass judgment upon God’s law. Theonomy, and theonomy alone, must be the standard of Christian ethics. The sole Law-giver and Judge is God. Hence God’s law must be the criterion by which we evaluate the secular systems of ethics. The "goodness" of God and absolute authority of His word are a priori presuppositions for the Christian. The clay cannot talk back to the potter (Isa. 45:9), and the vassals have no right to question the Lord (cf. Matt. 20:1 ff.). We will be blessed only if we faithfully obey the directives of our God without questioning His word, just as Abraham did (Gen. 22:1 ff.; Heb. 11:17 ff.). When Job demands an interview with God, it is God who does the questioning, thereby asserting His sovereign Lordship and affirming that man cannot call Him into question (1ob 38-42). "Let God be true and every man a liar" (Rom. 3:4), for "His work is perfect, for all His ways are just; a God of faithfulness and without injustice, righ [306] teous and upright is He" (Deut. 32:4, NASV). The only foundation for a Christian ethic, and hence the only foundation for any genuine and true morality, is the holy law of God.  
Theonomy is pitted against autonomy; no man can take stand in between, for no man can serve two masters (Matt. 6:24). The authority and righteousness of God must be asserted against any and all serpents who question His goodness and veracity. Even if God should ask that we sacrifice the only son of promise, we must never demur or question; His revealed will alone defines the righteousness which is becoming of the believer (cf. Gen. 22; Heb. 11:17-19). We do not attempt to be as God, determining good and evil; rather, we gladly take our place beneath the sovereign Lordship of the Triune God. His word, not our autonomous reasoning, is our law. Theonomy is the exclusive normative principle, the only standard, of Christian ethics. It is all or nothing, ethic or nonethic, obedience or sin  


The
Christmas Conspiracy


Virtue


Vine & Fig Tree


Paradigm Shift


Theocracy


End The Wall of Separation
Mailing List

Enter your e-mail address:
Browse the Theocracy Archive
An e-group hosted by eGroups.com

Vine & Fig Tree
12314 Palm Dr. #107
Desert Hot Springs, CA 92240
[e-mail to V&FT]
[V&FT Home Page]